Traditional Knowledge & Justifiable Obtainability
The participant that receives the most points from the voters is declared a winner.
Voting will end in:
- Publication date
- Last updated date
- Type
- Rated
- Number of rounds
- 5
- Time for argument
- One week
- Max argument characters
- 10,000
- Voting period
- Two months
- Point system
- Multiple criterions
- Voting system
- Open
- Minimal rating
- None
PRO's claim: All traditional knowledge is a justifiably obtainable thing or some traditional knowledge is a justifiably obtainable thing.
CON's claim: No traditional knowledge is a justifiably obtainable thing.
Stipulations:
1) All traditional knowledge is a justified true belief.
2) When mentioning knowledge without "traditional," it is assumed that "traditional knowledge" is meant.
3) Although laws of logic are not necessarily propositions, they can become propositions or claims. For example, "no existence is contradicting" is the law of contradiction (LNC), and the format given is a proposition. That is the treatment of the laws of logic within this debate.
Please see my three recent debates to understand how CON constructs their opening statement.
- All traditional knowledge is a justified true belief.
The stances here are relatively straightforward. I am to make the case that at least some traditional knowledge is justifiably obtainable.
Knowledge
First what is knowledge? Con stipulates that all knowledge is "a justified true belief." This is correct. Minimally, to know is to have a belief, that is true, and that is held with good reason (justified). I will abbreviate "justified true belief" as JTB.
As JTB is a necessary condition for knowledge, all knowledge is JTB, but JTB is not sufficient for knowledge; more is needed. To show this, consider the Gettier problem in epistemology, where a range of counterexamples demonstrate cases where we have JTB but not knowledge.
The sheep in the field (Chisholm 1966/1977/1989). Imagine that you are standing outside a field. You see, within it, what looks exactly like a sheep. What belief instantly occurs to you? Among the many that could have done so, it happens to be the belief that there is a sheep in the field. And in fact, you are right, because there is a sheep behind the hill in the middle of the field. You cannot see that sheep, though, and you have no direct evidence of its existence. Moreover, what you are seeing is a dog, disguised as a sheep. Hence, you have a well-justified true belief that there is a sheep in the field. But is that belief knowledge?
(1) Person S believes that P
(2) P is true
(3) S is justified in believing that P
(4) S's belief that P is not vulnerable to a Gettier case
My case
I am tasked with the simple burden of showing that some, at least one, case of traditional knowledge is justifiably obtainable. Now that we have conditions for knowledge, the simple procedure shows that each condition is satisfied.
Paradigmatic cases
I believe that bachelors are unmarried men as many do, so the belief condition is satisfied. It is also true that bachelors are unmarried men, by definition. I also have good reason to think this is true, namely, that I can directly apprehend the meanings of the terms I use because meanings are determined by the intentions of speakers. Lastly, this is not a Gettier case. My belief was not formed or justified by accident, hence, I know that bachelors are unmarried men. This argument generalizes to truths like "2+2=4" and "a tiger is a tiger."
My argument did not depend on the law of noncontradiction or the law of excluded middle. In fact, these principles are on shaky ground as I will explain.
Another argument is that my position is more modest. I claim that at least one belief has certain properties and con denies that any belief does. Without considering anything the prior probability of my thesis is much higher, for it is much more modest. If a hundred coins are being flipped, if person A claims they will all land on heads, and B claims that at least one will be tails we would all believe B because his theory is more modest and far more likely to be true. The same applies here.
Rebuttals
Pro starts with four claims:
1. Every begging question is the fallacy of unwarranted assumption that either assumes the truth of a conclusion in the course of trying to prove it or assumes the truth of a contentious claim.2. Every fallacy is a poor form of reasoning.3. Every justification is a good reason for a belief.4. Every law of logic is a rule that underlies thinking itself.
We should be cautious about 2 because there are many "informal fallacies" that may not necessarily be cases of poor reasoning at all, and many different references have different lists of which fallacies there are. As I will go on to argue, begging the question may not always be unjustified, and plausibly is in some cases.
4 is just unsupported. Laws of logic like the law of non-contradiction (no proposition is both true and false) and the excluded middle (every proposition is either true or false) aren't presupposed in ordinary reasoning. For instance, we often don't think that propositions like "John is bald" or "It is noonish" are only possibly either true or false as they are cases of semantic vagueness, and may have indeterminate truth values.
Many semantic paradoxes plausibly violate the law of noncontradiction. Consider the following:
Consider the sentence: ‘This sentence is not true’. There are two options: either the sentence is true or it is not. Suppose it is true. Then what it says is the case. Hence the sentence is not true. Suppose, on the other hand, it is not true. This is what it says. Hence the sentence is true. In either case it is both true and not true.
From this, these statement of cons:
Proposition 2.3. EVERY JUSTIFIED TRUE BELIEF IS A THING THAT PRESUMES THE TRUTH OF THE LAWS OF LOGIC AS A NECESSITY.Proposition 2.3. EVERY JUSTIFIED TRUE BELIEF IS A THING THAT PRESUMES THE TRUTH OF THE LAWS OF LOGIC AS A NECESSITY.
Proposition 1.5. EVERY LAW OF LOGIC IS A THING THAT JUSTIFIES ITSELF.
Proposition 1.6. EVERY LAW OF LOGIC IS BEGGING THE QUESTION.
From this cons argument for:
Proposition 1.7. NO LAW OF LOGIC IS JUSTIFIED.
Con's arguments require this idea that we somehow always assume the laws of logic that he identifies in our reasoning, and that these are unjustified. I have raised objections to both points, first that we make these presumptions, or that reasoning requires them, and second, that if these laws were true, we would have to beg the question to come to that conclusion.
Now on begging the question (BTQ), if BTQ is any form of circular inference, con bears the burden of showing that there is no plausible notion of virtuous epistemic circularity, on which a lot of philosophical work has been done in the field of epistemology. Epistemologist Ernest Sosa notes that the coherence of beliefs in webs of beliefs may have justification conferring properties even if they all depend on one another.
One kind of justification-conferring coherence is among beliefs of the same order. For example, coherence among object-level beliefs, especially explanatory coherence, can boost one’s degree of justification for those beliefs. Another kind of justification-conferring coherence is among beliefs at different orders or levels. For example, one might have a coherent explanation regarding how one’s object-level belief is reliably formed, and hence likely to be true.
The first sort we might call “source circularity”: any fully general epistemology must investigate all of our knowledge-conferring sources. But then any such investigation will proceed by exploiting those very sources... As Sosa notes, this does not point to some weakness or defect in the human condition—it is rather the logical consequence of a fully general epistemology...A second kind of benign circularity might be called “coverage circularity”: Any fully general criterion for some epistemic status will cover itself, if it is supposed to itself have that epistemic status. For example, a general criterion might specify necessary and sufficient conditions for justification...But then a justified belief that the criterion is correct will also have to meet those very conditions.
Conclusion
My case is simple. There are paradigmatic cases of analytic truths that we know. I have shown how these satisfy all the relevant conditions for knowledge. I also appeal to the modest and antecedent likelihood of my position, which itself is a strong reason to vote in its favor. Lastly, I show the flaws in all of cons arguments.
As JTB is a necessary condition for knowledge, all knowledge is JTB, but JTB is not sufficient for knowledge; more is needed. To show this, consider the Gettier problem in epistemology, where a range of counterexamples demonstrate cases where we have JTB but not knowledge.
Proposition 1.6. EVERY LAW OF LOGIC IS BEGGING THE QUESTION.is just confusion about begging the question which is a property of arguments, not propositions or sentences. An individual sentence like a law of logic cannot itself beg the question, but an argument for one could.
Proposition 1.6. EVERY LAW OF LOGIC IS BEGGING THE QUESTION.Everything that justifies itself is begging the question [Def 1.3], moreover, every law of logic is a thing that justifies itself [1.5]; therefore, every law of logic is begging the question.
I'll grant 1 and 3, and reject 2 and 4.
Every fallacy is a poor form of reasoning.
Every law of logic is a rule that underlies thinking itself.
...bachelors are unmarried men.
As I said in round 1, JTB is necessary, but not sufficient for knowledge.
Next, con seems to reject the charitable interpretation I offered for what the laws of logic are to their case. As a result of this, it becomes vague and unclear what con means by "the rules that underlie thinking itself" and con provides no further account of what these are supposed to be and what it means for a rule to "underlie thinking."
Exposing this unclarity becomes a theme in my response. I also explore the self-defeating nature of con's view. After all, con has conceded that their position is unjustified by his lights.
Notes
a. In my last round I distinguish between circularity and begging the question. By Con's own definition which I agreed with:
Every begging the question is fallacy of unwarranted assumption...
Even if we assume that part of what Con says is true, all he would have shown is that there is circularity. He has the burden of not only showing that there is this circularity, but that the circularity is unwarranted, such that it becomes begging the question.
As I stated before if con stipulates that all circularity IS begging the question, then I no longer agree to con's terms and they have the burden of showing that BTQ is always fallacious.
b. Con claims there is something that every argument presumes. Some sort of rule that remains a mystery, and con gives no specification of what this rule is or any evidence that every argument presumes it. This can be dismissed as no clarification has been provided and no argument has been given for it.
B. My case
I gave two arguments for there being at least one instance of justifiably obtainable traditional knowledge.
(i) The first consisted of giving paradigmatic examples that satisfy the conditions for knowledge as laid out. For example, we know things like "bachelors are unmarried" "tigers are tigers" and "1+1=2" etc. precisely because we have direct access to the meanings of terms in our language as we use them.
Pro says in response:
However, for my reasoning in the first R1 argument to be invalid PRO would need to assert that the justification used here is not controlled by the rules that underlie thinking itself.
First, this is confusion between validity and soundness. Second, con continues to employ this mysterious language about "rules that underlie thinking itself." They should be more specific—it's not clear what they are talking about. So, as of now, there has not been a rejoinder to my first argument.
But there seems to be some idea here that if arguments ultimately assume some principle, whatever that may be, then they could not justify. First, no evidence has been given that every argument assumes some principle or set of principles, and no evidence has been given that even if this were true, circularity is always unjustified. It also could be the case that there are just foundational principles that are justified non inferentially and con has done nothing to rule out that possibility.
(ii) The second argument was a simple examination of the prior probability of my side of the burden. Con in response says:
In terms of prior probability, CON's argument is clearly superior because it uses deductive logic in the first R1 argument.
This is frankly bizarre. Just because an argument is framed in a certain way does not make it "better" than an argument framed differently. The following argument is a deductive argument for example:
[1] If the sky is blue, then pigs fly
[2] The sky is blue
[3] Hence, pigs fly (1, 2)
But it is a terrible argument not better than the host of inductive arguments that support the theory of evolution, or the inductive inferences based on observations and recoded data from experiments in physics.
Just because an argument is presented deductively does not mean you have good reason to believe the premises are true. Similarly, an argument may be inductive, and provide excellent reasons to accept the premises and the conclusion.
As we can see, this does not respond to the argument from prior probability, so it may as well be extended. The likelihood that at least one instance of traditional knowledge is justifiably obtainable is much higher than the probability that none are whatsoever because the former is a much more modest and much weaker claim. For this reason alone, my position is apparent.
C. Rebuttals
Self Defeat
Con claims that no argument can justify the belief in a proposition. By his lights, no argument that con themself has given in this debate justifies belief in the claim he is defending.
If that's right, con concedes that their own position is unjustified, and thus concedes that they are unable to defend their position. So, con's position is self-defeating.
The voters should not vote for the debater who admits his own position is unjustified. Since has conceded their position is unjustified, the voters need not consider it.
Circularity/Begging the question
Pro seems to be confused about a lot. For one they say that:
However, subscribing to coherentism does not entail believing that the structure is justified.
Justification is not a property of the structure of justification, justification is a property of the beliefs we have, so this message is incoherent. They go on to assert that:
As PRO rightly argued, the begging question only applies to an argument or justification. Coherentism isn't an argument; it is a description of how justified beliefs interact.
This is a confusion about the point. Whether "begging the question" is always fallacious is in contention. Coherentism is an inferential theory of justification! This means that for the Coherentist, beliefs are justified by inferences also known as arguments, it is just permissible for those arguments to be circular if they appeal to coherence with a web of beliefs. Thus to defend the claim that begging the question is always unjustified, con carries the burden of showing that justification does not ever have a coherentist structure, and con has provided no evidence of this whatsoever.
I cited information about the research program on coherentism as a theory of justification in the philosophy of knowledge in my last post. Here is the dilemma:
On Con's definition of BTQ the circularity must be unwarranted. Either he shows that all cases of circularity are warranted in which case he bears a tall burden or he stipulates that all cases of circularity are begging the question of which case I reject such a stipulation, and he bears the burden of defending it.
Laws of logic
I provided a charitable interpretation of con in terms of the traditional classical laws of logic, but he insists this isn't right. Rather laws of logic are merely "rules that underly thinking itself" according to Con with no example or indication of what they could be talking about.
Logic is a pluralistic endeavor both mathematically, and in actual reasoning. There are different principles of logic used in mathematical proofs and ordinary reasoning in different contexts and no apparent reason to accept Con's broad claim that all reasoning assumes some specific set of principles. Con has provided no evidence for this claim whatsoever, and his argument hinges on it.
Aside from my interpretation, what con thinks a law of logic is becomes very vague. What is a "rule that underlies thinking itself?" What does con mean by "rule"—which is a notoriously polysemous notion that can refer to both descriptive and normative principles—in this context and what does it mean for one to "underly thinking?"
Con says:
The real issue is that the underlying rules of reasoning are not justified, a problem inherent to all formal systems of logic.
But what exactly does con mean by "underlying rules of reasoning" in the context of a formal system? Formal systems are composed of a formal language, which is a class of well-formed formulas, and a consequence relation modeled in its deduction system or its semantics, often both. In his next response, con should say what specifically the "underlying rules of reasoning" are in the mathematical system given that he is commenting on them as applied to formal systems.
Conclusion
Con misunderstands a lot of basic points of the debate. But some key points of contention remain:
(i) Circuarlity is always unjustified (unsupported)
(ii) All arguments assume some principle or a collection of principles (unsupported).
(iii) The vagueness of "the rules that underly thinking itself" which con has not explained nor given any examples of.
Even aside all this con must undermine all of my arguments—the second of which showing the extremely low probability of his view—overcome the self-defeat of his own position, and show that coherence justification and non-inferential justification are both impossible. This is starting to look like an untenable task for them.
This means that for circularity to be begging the question, it must be unwarranted. But if coherentism is right, there may be cases of circularity that are warranted based on propositions' role in a coherent web of beliefs.
Even if we assume that part of what Con says is true, all he would have shown is that there is circularity. He has the burden of not only showing that there is this circularity, but that the circularity is unwarranted, such that it becomes begging the question.
As I stated before if con stipulates that all circularity IS begging the question, then I no longer agree to con's terms and they have the burden of showing that BTQ is always fallacious.
However, subscribing to coherentism does not entail believing that the structure is justified.Justification is not a property of the structure of justification, justification is a property of the beliefs we have, so this message is incoherent. They go on to assert that:As PRO rightly argued, the begging question only applies to an argument or justification. Coherentism isn't an argument; it is a description of how justified beliefs interact.
This is a confusion about the point. Whether "begging the question" is always fallacious is in contention. Coherentism is an inferential theory of justification! This means that for the Coherentist, beliefs are justified by inferences also known as arguments, it is just permissible for those arguments to be circular if they appeal to coherence with a web of beliefs. Thus to defend the claim that begging the question is always unjustified, con carries the burden of showing that justification does not ever have a coherentist structure, and con has provided no evidence of this whatsoever.
b. Con claims there is something that every argument presumes. Some sort of rule that remains a mystery, and con gives no specification of what this rule is or any evidence that every argument presumes it. This can be dismissed as no clarification has been provided and no argument has been given for it....First, this is confusion between validity and soundness. Second, con continues to employ this mysterious language about "rules that underlie thinking itself." They should be more specific—it's not clear what they are talking about. So, as of now, there has not been a rejoinder to my first argument.But there seems to be some idea here that if arguments ultimately assume some principle, whatever that may be, then they could not justify. First, no evidence has been given that every argument assumes some principle or set of principles, and no evidence has been given that even if this were true, circularity is always unjustified. It also could be the case that there are just foundational principles that are justified non inferentially and con has done nothing to rule out that possibility....Logic is a pluralistic endeavor both mathematically, and in actual reasoning. There are different principles of logic used in mathematical proofs and ordinary reasoning in different contexts and no apparent reason to accept Con's broad claim that all reasoning assumes some specific set of principles. Con has provided no evidence for this claim whatsoever, and his argument hinges on it.
There are a host of formal systems that don't validate these principles such as para-complete, paraconsistent, relevant logics, etc
his next response, con should say what specifically the "underlying rules of reasoning" are in the mathematical system given that he is commenting on them as applied to formal systems.
- If a = b and c = d, then a + c = b + d; addition
- If a = b and c = d, then a − c = b − d; subtraction
- If a = b, then ca = cb; multiplication
- If a = b and c =/ 0, then a/c = b/c; division
- If a = b, then either a or b may be substituted for the other in any equation or inequality.
- a = a
- If a = b, then b = a.
- If a ≤ b, then b ≥ a.
- If a ≥ b, then b ≤ a.
- If a ≥ b and b ≥ c, then a ≥ c.
- If a ≤ b and b ≤ c, then a ≤ c.
- If a ≥ b and b > c, then a > c.
- If a = b and b > c, then a > c.
- If a ≤ b, then a + c ≤ b + c and a − c ≤ b − c.
- If a ≥ b, then a + c ≥ b + c and a − c ≥ b − c.
- If a ≥ b and c > 0, then ac ≥ bc and a/c ≥ b/c .
- If a ≤ b and c > 0, then ac ≤ bc and a/c ≤ b/c .
- If a ≥ b and c < 0, then ac ≤ bc and a/c ≤ b/c .
- If a ≤ b and c < 0, then ac ≥ bc and a/c ≥ b/c .
- If a ≤ b, then −a ≥ −b.
- If a ≥ b, then −a ≤ −b.
This is frankly bizarre. Just because an argument is framed in a certain way does not make it "better" than an argument framed differently. The following argument is a deductive argument for example:[1] If the sky is blue, then pigs fly[2] The sky is blue[3] Hence, pigs fly (1, 2)But it is a terrible argument not better than the host of inductive arguments that support the theory of evolution, or the inductive inferences based on observations and recoded data from experiments in physics.
Just because an argument is presented deductively does not mean you have good reason to believe the premises are true. Similarly, an argument may be inductive, and provide excellent reasons to accept the premises and the conclusion.
(i) Circuarlity is always unjustified (unsupported)
(ii) All arguments assume some principle or a collection of principles (unsupported).
(iii) The vagueness of "the rules that underly thinking itself" which con has not explained nor given any examples of.
Incorrect
never claimed all circularity is fallacious or begging the question
Notice this claim PRO is making, that if coherentism is true, then some circularity is warranted
name what formal system of logic PRO subscribes to
impossible to prove due to this limited medium and time constraint
But if coherentism is right, there may be cases of circularity that are warranted based on propositions' role in a coherent web of beliefs.
(i) The first consisted of giving paradigmatic examples that satisfy the conditions for knowledge as laid out. For example, we know things like "bachelors are unmarried" "tigers are tigers" and "1+1=2" etc. precisely because we have direct access to the meanings of terms in our language as we use them.
...my position is more modest. I claim that at least one belief has certain properties and con denies that any belief does. Without considering anything the prior probability of my thesis is much higher, for it is much more modest. If a hundred coins are being flipped, if person A claims they will all land on heads, and B claims that at least one will be tails we would all believe B because his theory is more modest and far more likely to be true. The same applies here.
Just because an argument is presented deductively does not mean you have good reason to believe the premises are true. Similarly, an argument may be inductive, and provide excellent reasons to accept the premises and the conclusion.
It is impossible to prove due to this limited medium and time constraint
Novice is back ^^
Case and point.
Couldn't it be that I merely did not enjoy debating you much?
All of you that run, block , I get under your skin.
Who's the "other one"?
Another one I got on the run.