Traditional Knowledge & Justifiable Obtainability
Waiting for the next argument from the contender.
Round will be automatically forfeited in:
- Publication date
- Last updated date
- Type
- Rated
- Number of rounds
- 5
- Time for argument
- One week
- Max argument characters
- 10,000
- Voting period
- Two months
- Point system
- Multiple criterions
- Voting system
- Open
- Minimal rating
- None
PRO's claim: All traditional knowledge is a justifiably obtainable thing or some traditional knowledge is a justifiably obtainable thing.
CON's claim: No traditional knowledge is a justifiably obtainable thing.
Stipulations:
1) All traditional knowledge is a justified true belief.
2) When mentioning knowledge without "traditional," it is assumed that "traditional knowledge" is meant.
3) Although laws of logic are not necessarily propositions, they can become propositions or claims. For example, "no existence is contradicting" is the law of contradiction (LNC), and the format given is a proposition. That is the treatment of the laws of logic within this debate.
Please see my three recent debates to understand how CON constructs their opening statement.
- All traditional knowledge is a justified true belief.
The stances here are relatively straightforward. I am to make the case that at least some traditional knowledge is justifiably obtainable.
Knowledge
First what is knowledge? Con stipulates that all knowledge is "a justified true belief." This is correct. Minimally, to know is to have a belief, that is true, and that is held with good reason (justified). I will abbreviate "justified true belief" as JTB.
As JTB is a necessary condition for knowledge, all knowledge is JTB, but JTB is not sufficient for knowledge; more is needed. To show this, consider the Gettier problem in epistemology, where a range of counterexamples demonstrate cases where we have JTB but not knowledge.
The sheep in the field (Chisholm 1966/1977/1989). Imagine that you are standing outside a field. You see, within it, what looks exactly like a sheep. What belief instantly occurs to you? Among the many that could have done so, it happens to be the belief that there is a sheep in the field. And in fact, you are right, because there is a sheep behind the hill in the middle of the field. You cannot see that sheep, though, and you have no direct evidence of its existence. Moreover, what you are seeing is a dog, disguised as a sheep. Hence, you have a well-justified true belief that there is a sheep in the field. But is that belief knowledge?
(1) Person S believes that P
(2) P is true
(3) S is justified in believing that P
(4) S's belief that P is not vulnerable to a Gettier case
My case
I am tasked with the simple burden of showing that some, at least one, case of traditional knowledge is justifiably obtainable. Now that we have conditions for knowledge, the simple procedure shows that each condition is satisfied.
Paradigmatic cases
I believe that bachelors are unmarried men as many do, so the belief condition is satisfied. It is also true that bachelors are unmarried men, by definition. I also have good reason to think this is true, namely, that I can directly apprehend the meanings of the terms I use because meanings are determined by the intentions of speakers. Lastly, this is not a Gettier case. My belief was not formed or justified by accident, hence, I know that bachelors are unmarried men. This argument generalizes to truths like "2+2=4" and "a tiger is a tiger."
My argument did not depend on the law of noncontradiction or the law of excluded middle. In fact, these principles are on shaky ground as I will explain.
Another argument is that my position is more modest. I claim that at least one belief has certain properties and con denies that any belief does. Without considering anything the prior probability of my thesis is much higher, for it is much more modest. If a hundred coins are being flipped, if person A claims they will all land on heads, and B claims that at least one will be tails we would all believe B because his theory is more modest and far more likely to be true. The same applies here.
Rebuttals
Pro starts with four claims:
1. Every begging question is the fallacy of unwarranted assumption that either assumes the truth of a conclusion in the course of trying to prove it or assumes the truth of a contentious claim.2. Every fallacy is a poor form of reasoning.3. Every justification is a good reason for a belief.4. Every law of logic is a rule that underlies thinking itself.
We should be cautious about 2 because there are many "informal fallacies" that may not necessarily be cases of poor reasoning at all, and many different references have different lists of which fallacies there are. As I will go on to argue, begging the question may not always be unjustified, and plausibly is in some cases.
4 is just unsupported. Laws of logic like the law of non-contradiction (no proposition is both true and false) and the excluded middle (every proposition is either true or false) aren't presupposed in ordinary reasoning. For instance, we often don't think that propositions like "John is bald" or "It is noonish" are only possibly either true or false as they are cases of semantic vagueness, and may have indeterminate truth values.
Many semantic paradoxes plausibly violate the law of noncontradiction. Consider the following:
Consider the sentence: ‘This sentence is not true’. There are two options: either the sentence is true or it is not. Suppose it is true. Then what it says is the case. Hence the sentence is not true. Suppose, on the other hand, it is not true. This is what it says. Hence the sentence is true. In either case it is both true and not true.
From this, these statement of cons:
Proposition 2.3. EVERY JUSTIFIED TRUE BELIEF IS A THING THAT PRESUMES THE TRUTH OF THE LAWS OF LOGIC AS A NECESSITY.Proposition 2.3. EVERY JUSTIFIED TRUE BELIEF IS A THING THAT PRESUMES THE TRUTH OF THE LAWS OF LOGIC AS A NECESSITY.
Proposition 1.5. EVERY LAW OF LOGIC IS A THING THAT JUSTIFIES ITSELF.
Proposition 1.6. EVERY LAW OF LOGIC IS BEGGING THE QUESTION.
From this cons argument for:
Proposition 1.7. NO LAW OF LOGIC IS JUSTIFIED.
Con's arguments require this idea that we somehow always assume the laws of logic that he identifies in our reasoning, and that these are unjustified. I have raised objections to both points, first that we make these presumptions, or that reasoning requires them, and second, that if these laws were true, we would have to beg the question to come to that conclusion.
Now on begging the question (BTQ), if BTQ is any form of circular inference, con bears the burden of showing that there is no plausible notion of virtuous epistemic circularity, on which a lot of philosophical work has been done in the field of epistemology. Epistemologist Ernest Sosa notes that the coherence of beliefs in webs of beliefs may have justification conferring properties even if they all depend on one another.
One kind of justification-conferring coherence is among beliefs of the same order. For example, coherence among object-level beliefs, especially explanatory coherence, can boost one’s degree of justification for those beliefs. Another kind of justification-conferring coherence is among beliefs at different orders or levels. For example, one might have a coherent explanation regarding how one’s object-level belief is reliably formed, and hence likely to be true.
The first sort we might call “source circularity”: any fully general epistemology must investigate all of our knowledge-conferring sources. But then any such investigation will proceed by exploiting those very sources... As Sosa notes, this does not point to some weakness or defect in the human condition—it is rather the logical consequence of a fully general epistemology...A second kind of benign circularity might be called “coverage circularity”: Any fully general criterion for some epistemic status will cover itself, if it is supposed to itself have that epistemic status. For example, a general criterion might specify necessary and sufficient conditions for justification...But then a justified belief that the criterion is correct will also have to meet those very conditions.
Conclusion
My case is simple. There are paradigmatic cases of analytic truths that we know. I have shown how these satisfy all the relevant conditions for knowledge. I also appeal to the modest and antecedent likelihood of my position, which itself is a strong reason to vote in its favor. Lastly, I show the flaws in all of cons arguments.
As JTB is a necessary condition for knowledge, all knowledge is JTB, but JTB is not sufficient for knowledge; more is needed. To show this, consider the Gettier problem in epistemology, where a range of counterexamples demonstrate cases where we have JTB but not knowledge.
Proposition 1.6. EVERY LAW OF LOGIC IS BEGGING THE QUESTION.is just confusion about begging the question which is a property of arguments, not propositions or sentences. An individual sentence like a law of logic cannot itself beg the question, but an argument for one could.
Proposition 1.6. EVERY LAW OF LOGIC IS BEGGING THE QUESTION.Everything that justifies itself is begging the question [Def 1.3], moreover, every law of logic is a thing that justifies itself [1.5]; therefore, every law of logic is begging the question.
I'll grant 1 and 3, and reject 2 and 4.
Every fallacy is a poor form of reasoning.
Every law of logic is a rule that underlies thinking itself.
...bachelors are unmarried men.
Novice is back ^^
Case and point.
Couldn't it be that I merely did not enjoy debating you much?
All of you that run, block , I get under your skin.
Who's the "other one"?
Another one I got on the run.